Folder Classification

What is a classification?

Classification is the ordering of similar entities (objects) in a hierarchical series of nested classes, in which each more inclusive higher-level class is subdivided comprehensively into less inclusive classes at the next lower leve

In biological classifications, the ordered grouping of organisms into classes accords to their similarities and is consistent with the evolutionary history of the organisms in the group. The latter is inferred from their taxonomic characters.

Why do we need classification

The complexity of the living world - be it at genetic, organism or ecosystem level - is so large that scientific explanations become possible only after the diversity is reduced to understandable, manageable groupings. This is achieved through the process of biological classification that has the following objectives:

 

  • it sorts similar and/or related taxa into groups and delimits these against other such groups; 
  • it serves as the summary of the information contained in the groups; 
  • it serves to retrieve information; 
  • it serves as the basis for comparative research. 

 

Biological classification is thus concerned with the hierarchical ordering of organisms into objective (principled) hierarchical groups.

How are classifications made?

Basically there exist two fundamentally different methods of biological classification: phenetics and cladistics. Prior to discussing the differences between both systematic approaches it is worthwhile to mention that both methods deal with as much characters (and their character states) as possible and thus are fundamentally different from the essentialistic/typological methods of the ancients that concentrated only on a limited number of key-characters.

Phenetics, also termed numerical taxonomy, departs from the philosophy that the phylogeny of organisms can never be known to satisfaction and that it thus cannot be used in biological classification. As such, pheneticists argue that grouping by overall similarity is the most objective option to achieve a natural classification. According to the phenetic approach such is possible by considering as much characters as possible and giving each the same weight (or importance). Multivariate statistics on the whole set of character states yields a hierarchical phenogram. It is the topology of that phenogram that dictates the hierarchical classification whereby arbitrary chosen similarity coefficients determine the ranks in the classification.

Cladistics departs from the fact that phylogenetic relationship is the only valid principle by which organisms can be classified. The three basic criterions of cladistics are: apomorphy, monophyly and parsimony. An apomorphy is a derived character state. Shared derived character states (=synapomorphies) define the taxa that are most closely related by common ancestry. Monophyly is the term used for a group of taxa that all share the same common ancestor, all the descendants of that ancestor must be included. Parsimony departs from the hypothesis that evolution is a rare phenomenon and that evolutionary pathway thus has to be as simple as possible, that is requiring the fewest number of steps. The branching diagrams produced with caldistic methods are called cladograms whereby each node represent a speciation event.

Course

(under construction)

References 

 

  • Avise, J.C. & Wollenberg, K. 1997. Phylogenetics and the origin of species. PNAS 94: 7748-7755.
  • Backeljau, T. et al. 1996. Multiple UPGMA and Neigbor-joining Trees and the Performance of Some Computer Packages. Moecular Biology & Evolution 13: 309-313.
  • Bailenson, J.N. et al. 2002. A bird's eye view: biological categorization and reasoning within and across cultures. Cognition 84: 1-53.
  • Barraclough, T.G. & Nee, S. 2001. Phylogenetics and speciation. TRENDS in Ecology and Evolution 16: 391-399.
  • Baum, D.A., DeWitt, S. & Donovan, S.S.S. 2005. The Tree-Thinking Challenge. Science 310: 979-980.
  • Cunningham, C.W., Omland, K.E. & Oakley, T.H. 1998. Reconstructing ancestral character states: a critical reappraisal. TRENDS in Ecology and Evolution 13: 361-366.
  • Ereshefsky, M. 2001. Names, Numbers and Indentations: A Guide to Post-Linnean Taxonomy. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Science 32: 361-383.
  • Ereshefsky, M. 2001. Philosophy of Biological Classification. Encyclopedia of Life Sciences 3.
  • Fitzhugh, K. 2006. The 'requirement of total evidence' and its role in phylogenetic systematics. Biology and Philosophy 21: 309-351.
  • Hull, D.L. 2001. The role of Theories in Biological Systematics. Stud. Hist. Phil. Biol. & Biomed. Sci. 32 (2): 221-238.
  • Johnson, L.A.S. 2004. From species to supertrees: Popperian corroboration and some current controversies in systematics. Australian Systematics Botany 17: 1-16.
  • Lecointre, G. & Tillier, S. 2001. Il faut renouveler la systématique. Pour la Science 285: 7.
  • Lopéz, A. & Atran, S. 1997. The Tree of Life: Universal and Cultural Features of Folkbiological Taxonomies and Inductions. Cognitive Psychology 32: 251-295.
  • Mallatt, J. & Winchell, C.J. 2002. Testing the New Animal Phylogeny: First Use of Combined Large-Subunit and Small-Subunit rRNA Gene Sequences to Classify the Protostomes. Mol.Biol.Evol. 19: 289-301.
  • Marshall, E. 2005. Will DNA bar codes breathe life into classification? Science 307: 1037.
  • Mayr E., Bock W.J. 2002. Classifications and other ordering systems. J. Zool. Syst. Evol. Research 40: 169-194.
  • Minelli, A. 2002. Classification. Encyclopedia of Life Sciences, 5 pp.
  • Nixon, K.C. & Carpenter, J.M. 2000. On the Other "Phylogenetic Systematics". Cladistics 16: 298-318.
  • Page, R.D.M. & Charleston, M.A. 1998. Trees within trees: phylogeny and historical associations. TRENDS in Ecology and Evolution 13: 356-359.
  • Prance T. 2001. The Relevance of Systematics to the Twenty-first Century. Encyclopedia of Life Sciences, 7pp.
  • Rieppel, O. 2005. Proper names in twin worlds: Monophyly, paraphyly, and the world around us. Organisms, Diversity and Evolution 5: 89-100.
  • Sereno, P.C. 2005. The Logical Basis of Phylogenetic Taxonomy. Systematic Biology 54: 595-619.
  • Slowinski, J.B. & Page, R.D.M. 1999. How should species Phylogenies be inferred from sequence data? Syst.Biol. 48: 814-825. Sokal, R.R. 1966. Numerical Taxonomy. Scientific American 215 (6): 106-116.
  • Sokal, R.R. 1974. Classification: Purposes, Principles, Progress, Prospects. Science 185: 1115-1123.
  • Stevens, P.F. 2002. History of Taxonomy. Encyclopedia of Life Sciences 3.
  • Tautz, D. et al.. 2003. A plea for DNA taxonomy. TRENDS in Ecology and Evolution 18: 70-74.
  • Telford, M.J. 2006. Animal Phylogeny. Current Biology 16: 981-985.
  • Vernon, K. 1988. The Founding of Numerical Taxonomy. BJHS 21: 143-159.
  • Vernon, K. 1993. Desperately seeking status: Evolutionary Systematics and the taxonomists' search for respectability. BJHS 26: 207-227.
  • Vernon, K. 1993. Desperately seeking status: Evolutionary Systematics and the taxonomists' search for respectability. BJHS 26: 207-227.
  • Vernon, K. 2001. A Truly Taxonomic Revolution? Numerical taxonomy 1957-1970. Stud. Hist. Phil. Biol. & Biomed. Sci 32(2): 315-341.
  • Wilkinson, M. 2002. Cladistics. Encyclopedia of Life Sciences 4.
  • Winsor, M.P. 2000. Species, Demes, and the Omega Taxonomy: Gilmour and The New Systematics. Biology and Philosophy 15: 349-388.
  • Winsor, M.P. 2003. Non-essentialist methods in pre-Darwinian taxonomy. Biology and Philosophy 18: 387-400.
  • Wolff, P., Medin, D.L. & Pankratz, C. 1999. Evolution and devolution of folkbiological knowledge. Cognition 73: 177-204.